HISTORY OF ANCIENT GREECE |
A HISTORY OF GREECE TO THE DEATH OF ALEXANDER THE GREAT
CHAPTER IV.
THE UNION OF ATTICA AND THE FOUNDATION OF THE ATHENIAN
DEMOCRACY
Sect.
1. The Union of Attica
When recorded history begins, the story of Athens is
the story of Attica, the inhabitants of Attica are Athenians. But Attica, like
its neighbour Boeotia and other countries of Greece, was once occupied by a
number of independent states. Some of these little kingdoms are vaguely
remembered in legends which tell of the giant Pallas who ruled at Pallene under
the north-eastern slopes of Hymettus, of the dreaded Cephalus lord of the
southern region of Thoricus, or of Porphyrion of
mighty stature whose domain was at Athmonon under
Mount Pentelicus. The hill of Munychia was, in the
distant past, an island, and was crowned by a stronghold; the name Piraeus has been supposed to preserve
the memory of days when the lords of Munychia looked across to the mainland and
spoke of the “opposite shore.” At a later stage we find neighbouring villages uniting themselves together by political or religious bonds. Thus in
the north, beyond Pentelicus, Marathon and Oenoe and
two other towns formed a tetrapolis.
Again Piraeus, adjacent Phaleron, and two other
places joined in the common worship of the god Heracles, and were called the
Four-Villages. Of all the lordships between Mount Tetra-Cithacron and Cape Sunium the two most important were
those of Eleusis and Athens, severed from one another by the hill-chain of Aegaleos
It was upon Athens, the stronghold in the midst of the
Cephisian plain, five miles from the sea, that destiny devolved the task of
working out the unity of Attica. This Cephisian plain, on the south side open
to the Saronic Gulf, is enclosed by hills, on the west by Aegaleos,
on the north-west by Pames, on the east by Hymettus,
while the gap in the north-east, between Pames and
Hymettus, is filled by the gableshaped mass of Pentelicus. The river Cephisus flows not far from Athens to
westward, but the Acropolis was girt by two smaller streams, the Ilisus and the
Eridanus. We have seen that it had been occupied as an abode of men in the
third millennium, and that in the bronze age it was one of the strong places of
Greece. There still remain pieces of the wall of grey-blue limestone with which
the Pelasgian lords of the castle secured the edge of their precipitous hill.
The old wall was called the Pelargikon, but in later
times this name was specially applied to the ground on the north-western slope.
The Acropolis is joined to the Areopagus by a high saddle, which forms its
natural approach, and on this side walls were so constructed that the main
western entrance to the citadel lay through nine successive gates. At the
north-western corner a covered staircase led down to the well of Clepsydra,
which supplied the fortress with water; and on the north side there were two
narrow “postern” descents into the plain, much steeper than that at Tiryns. We
may take it that all these constructions were the work of the Pelasgians and
were inherited by their Greek successors.
The first Greeks who won the Pelasgic acropolis were probably the Cecropes, and, though their name was forgotten as
the name of an independent people, it survived in another form. For the later
Athenians were always ready to describe themselves as the sons of Cecrops. This
Cecrops was numbered among the imaginary prehistoric kings of Athens; he was
nothing more than the fabulous ancestor of the Cecropes. But the time came when
other Greek dwellers in Attica won the upper hand over the Cecropes, and
brought with them the worship of Athena. It was a momentous day in the history
of the land when the goddess, whose cult was already established in many other
Attic places, took possession of the hill which was to be pre-eminently, and
for all time, associated with her name. The Acropolis became Athenai; the folks—whether Cecropes or Pelasgians—who
dwelled in the villages around it, on the banks of the Ilisus and Eridinus, became Athenians. The god whom the Cecropes
worshipped on the hill, Poseidon Erechtheus, was forced to give way to the
goddess. Legend told that Athena and Poseidon had disputed the possession of
the Acropolis, and that each had set a token there, the goddess her sacred
olive-tree, the god a salt-spring. The dethroned deity was not banished; there
was a conciliation, characteristic of the Greek temper, between the old and the
new. Erechtheus in the shape of a snake is permitted still to live on the hill
of Athena, and the oldest temple that was built for the goddess, harboured also the god. In later times Athenian “history”
transformed Erechtheus into a hero, and regarded him, like Cecrops, as one of
the early kings.
There was another god who was closely associated in
Attic legend with Athena, and Athens was distinguished by the high honour Athenian in which she held him. This was Hephaestus,
the divine smith, the master and helper of handicraftsmen, the cunning giver of
wealth. But we cannot say how far back his worship in Attica goes, or when his
special feasts were instituted. It is probable that his honour grew along with the prosperity of the craftsmen. Athenian poet calls his
countrymen “sons of Hephaestus,” and, according to one myth, it was from his
seed that all the earth-born inhabitants of Attica were sprung. At the feast of Apaturia, in the last days of autumn, when children
were admitted into the Phratries by a solemn ceremony, the fathers used to
light torches at the hearth and sing a hymn to the lord of fire.
The next great step in Attic history was the union of
the land. We cannot be certain at what time this union took place; it recedes
beyond the beginnings of recorded history; and we can only dimly discern how it
was brought about. When the lords of the Acropolis had subdued their own
Cephisian plain, from Mount Parnes to the hill of Munychia, from the slopes of
Hymettus to Aegaleos, they were tempted to extend
their power eastward into the “ Midlands ” beyond Mount Hymettus, and subdue
the southern “acté,” or wedge of land which ends in
the lofty cape of Sunium. The completion of this
conquest was possibly the first great achievement of Athens, and the second was
probably the subjugation of the north-eastern plain of Marathon and the “tetrapolis.” Thus the first stage in the union of Attica is
the reduction of the small independent sovereignties throughout all the land,
except the Eleusinian plain in the west, under the loose overlordship of
Athens.
In the course of time the feeling of unity in Attica
became so strong that all the smaller lordships, which formed parts of the
large state, but still retained their separate political organisations,
could be induced to surrender their home governments and merge themselves in a
single community with a government centralised in the
city of the Cephisian plain. The man of Thoricus or
Aphidnae or Icaria now became a citizen of Athens and his political rights must
be exercised there. The memory of this synoecism was preserved in historical times by an annual feast, and it was fitting that
it should be so remembered, for it determined the whole history of Athens. From
this time forward she is no longer merely the supreme city of Attica. She is
neither the head of a league of partly independent states, nor is she a
despotic mistress of subject-communities. She is not what Thebes is to become
in Boeotia, or what Sparta is in Laconia. If she had been, and she might well
have been, either of these things, her history would have been gravely altered.
She is the central city of an united state; and to the people of every village
in Attica belong the same political rights as to the people of Athens herself.
The man of Marathon or the man of Thoricus is no
longer an Attic, he is an Athenian. It is generally supposed that the synoecism was the work of one of the
kings. It was undoubtedly the work of one man; but it is possible that it
belongs to the period immediately succeeding the abolition of the royal power.
In after-times the Athenians thought that the hero
Theseus, whom they had enrolled in the list of their early kings, was the
author of the union of their country. But at the period when that union was
brought about Theseus was not a national hero. He was a local god, worshipped
in the Marathonian district and in the east coastlands of Attica; he had not
yet won the importance which he was to possess hereafter in Athenian myth and
history.
Sect.
2. Foundation of the Athenian Commonwealth
The early history of the Athenian constitution
resembles that of most other Greek states, in the general fact that a royalty,
subjected to various restrictions, passes into an aristocracy. But the details
of the transition are peculiar and the beginning of the republic seems to have
been exceptionally early. The traditional names of the Attic kings who came
after the hero Theseus are certainly in some cases, and, it may be, in most
cases, fictitious, the most famous of them being the Neleid Codrus, who was said to have sacrificed himself to
save his country on the occasion of an attack of invaders from the
Peloponnesus. The Athenians said that they had abolished royalty, on the death
of Codrus, because he was too good to have a
successor—a curious reversal of the usual causes of such a revolution. But this
story is a late invention. The first limitation of the royal power effected by
the aristocracy was the institution of a polemarch or military commander. The supreme command of the army, which had belonged to
the king, was transferred to him and he was elected from and by the nobles. The
next step seems to have been the overthrow of the royal house by the powerful
family of the Medontids. The Medontids did not themselves assume the royal
title, nor did they abolish it. They instituted the office of archon or regent, and this office
usurped the most important functions of the king, Acastus, the Medontid, was the first regent. We know that he was an
historical person; the archons of later days always swore that they would be
true to their oath even as Acastus. He held the post of Medon, for life, and
his successors after him; and thus the Medontids resembled kings, though they
did not bear the kingly name. But they fell short of royalty in another way
too; for each regent was elected by the community; the community was only bound
to elect a member of the Medontid family. The next
step in weakening the power of this kingly magistrate was the change of the
regency from a life office to an office of ten years. This reform is said to
have been effected about the middle of the eighth century. It is uncertain at
what time the Medontids were deprived of their prerogative and the regency was
thrown open to all the nobles. With the next step we reach firmer ground. The
regency became a yearly office, and from this time onward an official list of
the archons seems to have been preserved.
But meanwhile there were still kings at Athens. The
Medontids had robbed the kings of their royal power, but they had not done away
with the kings; there was to be a king at Athens till the latest days of the
Athenian democracy. It seems probable that, as some historical analogies might
suggest, the Medontids allowed the shadow of royalty to remain in the
possession of the old royal house, so that for some time there would have been
life-kings existing by the side of the life-regents; it is not likely that from
the very first the kingship was degraded to be a yearly office, filled by
election. This, however, was what it ultimately became.
The whole course of the constitutional development is
uncertain; for it rests upon traditions, of which it is extremely hard to judge
the value. But, whatever the details of the growth may have been, two important
facts are to be grasped One is that the fall of royalty, which does not imply
the abolition of the royal name, happened in Athens at an earlier period than
in Greece generally. The other is that the Medontids were not kings, but archons—the chiefs of an aristocracy.
The great work of the Medontids was the foundation of the Athenian
commonwealth; and perhaps one of their house is to be remembered for another
achievement, not less great, which has been already described, the union of
Attica.
That union need not be older than the ninth century,
and it is possible that the same republican movement which led to the downfall
of the old royal house of the Acropolis, led to the synoecism of Attica. The
political union of a country demands a system of organisation;
and the statesmen who united Attica sought their method of organisation from one of those cities of Ionia, which Athens came to look upon as her own
daughters. All the inhabitants were distributed into four tribes, which were
borrowed from Miletus. The curious names of these tribes—Geleontes,
Argadeis, Aigicoreis, and Hopletes—seem
to have been derived from the worship of special deities; for instance, Geleontes from Zeus Geleon. But
the original meanings of the names had entirely passed away, and the tribes
were affiliated to Apollo Patroos, the paternal
Apollo, from whom all Athenians claimed descent. The Brotherhoods seem to have
been reorganised and arranged under the tribes—three
to each tribe; so that there were twelve brotherhoods in the Attic state. At
the head of each tribe was a “tribe-king.”
We can see the clan organisation at Athens better than elsewhere. The families of each clan derived themselves
from a common ancestor, and most of the clan names are patronymics. The worship
of this ancestor was the chief end of the society. All the clans alike
worshipped Zeus Herkeios and Apollo Patroos; many of them had a special connexion with other public cults. Each had a regular administration and officers, at the
head of whom was an “archon.” To these clans only members of the noble families
belonged; but the other classes, the peasants and the craftsmen, formed similar organisations founded on the worship not of a common
The ancestor, for they could point to none, but some deity whom they chose. The
members of these were called orgeones. This innovation heralds the advance of the lower
classes to political importance.
The brotherhoods, composed of families whose lands
adjoined, united their members in the cult of Zeus Phratrios and Athena Phratria. In early times only clansmen
belonged to the brotherhoods, but here again a change takes place in the
seventh century, and orgeones are admitted. The organisation was then used for the
purposes of census. Every child whose parents were citizens must be admitted
into a brotherhood; and, if this rite is neglected, he is regarded as
illegitimate. It should be observed that illegitimacy at Athens did not deprive
a man of political rights, but he could not lay claim by right of birth to his
father’s inheritance.
At a much later time the constitutional historians of
Athens made out that the clans were artificial subdivisions of the
brotherhoods. They said that each tribe was divided into three brotherhoods,
each brotherhood into thirty clans, and it was even added that each clan
comprised thirty men. This artificial scheme is true, so far as the relation of
the tribe to the brotherhood is concerned; but it is not true in regard to the
clan, and is refuted by the circumstance that the tribes consisted of others than
clansmen.
Sect.
3. The Aristocracy in the Seventh Century
Early in the seventh century, then, the Athenian
republic was an aristocracy, and the executive was in the hands of three
annually elected officers, the archon, the king, and the polemarch. The archon
was the supreme judge in all civil
suits. When he entered on office, he published a declaration that he would,
throughout the term of his archonship, preserve the property of every citizen
intact. At a later time this sphere of judicial power was limited and he judged
mainly cases in which injured parents, orphans, heiresses were involved. He
held the chief place among the magistrates, having his official residence in
the Prytaneum where was the public hearth, and his name appeared at the head of
official lists, whence he was called eponymus; though the archonship was a later institution than
that of polemarch, as is shown by the fact that no old religious ceremonies
were performed by the archon, such as devolved upon the polemarch as well as
upon the king. But the conduct of festivals instituted at later times was
entrusted to him. Such were the Thargelia, the
late-May feast of the first-fruits, the chief Athenian feast of Apollo,
introduced from Delos probably in the seventh century; such were the great
Dionysia, which, as we shall see, were founded in the sixth. The polemarch had
judicial duties, besides being commander-in-chief of the army. He held a court
in the Epilykeion on the banks of the Ilisus, and
judged there all cases in which non-citizens were involved. Thus what the
archon was for citizens, the polemarch was for the class of foreign settlers
who were called “metics.” The king had his residence
in the royal Stoa in the Agora. His functions were confined to the management
of the state-religion, and the conduct of certain judicial cases connected
with religion. He was president of the Council, and thus had considerable power
and responsibility in the conduct of the judicial functions of that body.
The Bulé or Council was the
political organisation through which the nobles
carried out, at Athens as elsewhere, the gradual abolition of monarchy. This
Council of Elders — a part as we saw of the Aryan inheritance of the
Greeks—came afterwards to be called at Athens the Council of the Areopagus, to
distinguish it from other councils of later growth. This name was derived from
one of the Council’s most important functions. According to early custom, which
we find reflected in Homer, murder and manslaughter were not regarded as crimes
against the state, but concerned exclusively the family of the slain man, which
might either slay the slayer or accept a compensation. But gradually, as the
worship of the souls of the dead and the deities of the underworld developed,
the belief gained ground that he who shed blood was impure and needed
cleansing. Accordingly when a murderer satisfied the kinsfolk of the murdered
by paying a fine, he had also to submit to a process of purification, and
satisfy the Chthonian gods and the Erinyes or Furies, who were, in the original
conception, the souls of the dead clamouring for
vengeance. This notion of manslaughter as a religious offence necessarily led
to the interference of the state. For when the member of a community was
impure, the stain drew down the anger of the gods upon the whole community, if
the unclean were not driven out. Hence it came about that the state undertook
the conduct of criminal justice. The Council itself formed the court, and the
proceedings were closely associated with the worship of the Semnai. These Chthonian goddesses
had a sanctuary, which served as a refuge for him whose hand was stained with
bloodshed, on the northeast side of the Areopagus, outside the city wall. It
is possible that the association of this hill with the god Ares is merely due
to a popular etymology, for he had no shrine here; but the correct explanation
of the name Areiospagos is not known. On this rugged spot, apart
from but within sight of the dwellings of men, the Council held its sittings
for cases of murder, violence with murderous intent, poisoning, and
incendiarism. The accuser stood on the stone of Insolence, the accused on the
stone of Recklessness, each a huge unhewn block. This function of the Council,
which continued to belong to it after it had lost its other powers, procured it
the name of the Areopagus.
During the period of the aristocracy, the Council was
the governing body of Athens. We may be certain that the magistrates were
always members; but otherwise we do not know how it was composed, and therefore
can form no clear idea how the constitution worked. The Council doubtless
exercised direct control over the election of the chief magistrates; but we
need have small doubt that the king, the archon, and the polemarch were either
elected by the Ecclesia consisting of the whole body of citizens entitled to
vote, or at all events were chosen by the Council out of a limited number
nominated by the Assembly.
As an achievement of the aristocracy we may regard the
annexation of Eleusis. The Eleusinian kingdom bound in by Athens on one side
and Megara on the other—its little bay locked by Megarian Salamis—did not play
any part in any portion of Greek history of which we have the faintest record.
But of its independent existence we have a clear echo in a hymn which tells
the Eleusinian story of Demeter. That goddess, wandering in quest of her lost
daughter Persephone, came to Eleusis, where she was hospitably entertained by
the king, and would have made his infant son immortal but for the queen’s want
of faith. This poem is thought to have been composed in the seventh century,
and, if so, the days when Eleusis was independent had not yet passed out of
men’s memories then.
The middle of the seventh century is marked by a
further constitutional change, which is the result of various social changes.
The aristocracy of birth is forced to widen into an aristocracy of wealth. The
general causes of this change are to be found in the new economical conditions
which have been already pointed out as affecting the whole Greek world in the
seventh century. But to understand their operation and political consequences
at Athens, we must look more closely into the classes of the Attic population
and the social structure.
Under the rule of the kings and the aristocracies, the
free population fell into three classes: the Eupatridae or nobles; the Georgi or peasants who cultivated their
own farms; and the Demiurgi (public workers), those who lived by trade or commerce. The Eupatrids
originally lived in the country, and many Attic places were called from their
families, such as Paeonidae or Butadae.
After the synoecism, many of them came to live in the city. The Demiurgi had their settlements in the neighbourhood of the city—for example, there was the quarter of the “potters” north of the
Areopagus—and also villages in the country, such as Pelekes or Daedalidae.
But besides these classes of citizens, who had the right of attending the
Assembly, there was a mass of freemen who were not citizens. Among these we can
distinguish the agricultural labourers, who, having
no land of their own, cultivated the estates of the nobles. In return for their labour they retained one-sixth of the produce and
were hence called “Sixth-parters” (Hektemoroi). There were also the craftsmen who were
employed and paid by the Demiurgi, and doubtless
small retail dealers and others.
Although Attica seems to have taken no part in the colonising movements of the eighth and seventh centuries,
the Athenians shared in the trading activities of the period and were
profoundly affected by the economical revolution in the Greek world. The
cultivation of the olive was becoming a feature of Attica, and its oil a
profitable article of exportation. At the same time Attic potters were actively
developing their industry on lines of their own, and Attic pottery was in the
course of another century to become disseminated throughout the Mediterranean
countries from Tuscany to Cyprus. Jars of this age have been found in tombs
near the Dipylon gate on the north-west side of
Athens, and these Dipylon vases, as they are called,
give us a glimpse of the Attic civilisation of the
period. We not only see a new style of vase-painting, with geometrical ornament
and a symmetrical arrangement of the space at the painter’s disposal; but in
the pictures of funeral processions we can observe with what pomp and cost the
Attic nobles buried their dead. In the graves where these vases were found,
offerings were laid beside the dead, pottery and sometimes gold ornaments; and
the sepulchral pit was surmounted not by a mound but by a tall clay jar with an
opening below, through which drink offerings could be poured. But it must be
noticed that soon after this epoch, the influence of Ionia made itself felt in
Attica, and the custom was introduced of burning the dead; burial, however,
was not discontinued; the two customs subsisted side by side. Ionia also
affected Athenian dress. The woollen peplos fastened
with a pin was given up and the Ionian sleeved tunic or chiton, of linen, took
its place.
It would be interesting if we might see in the rude
representations of ships on some of the Dipylon vases
an illustration of the beginnings of Attic seamanship. The sea traffic of
Athens must have been rapidly growing in the first half of the seventh century.
It is easy to see how the active participation of Athens in trade began to
undermine the foundations of the aristocracy of birth, by introducing a new
standard of social distinction. The nobles engaged in mercantile ventures with
various success, some becoming richer, and others poorer; and the industrial
folk increased in wealth and importance. The result would ultimately be that
wealth would assert itself as well as birth, both socially and politically ;
and in the second half of the seventh century we find that, though the
aristocracy has not been fully replaced by a timocracy or constitution, in which political rights depend
entirely on wealth, all the conditions are present for such a transformation.
For we find the people divided into three classes according to their wealth.
The principle of division was the annual yield of landed property, in corn,
oil, or wine. The highest class was the Pentacosiomedimni. Before this name had any official meaning
it was perhaps in popular use to designate those large proprietors whose income
reached five hundred medimni of corn, at a time when
oil and wine had not been much cultivated. When it acquired an official sense,
it was defined to include those whose land produced at least so many measures (medimni) of com and so many measures (metretae)
of oil or wine as together amounted
to five hundred measures. The second class included those whose property
produced more than three hundred but less than five hundred such measures.
These were called Knights, and so represented roughly those who could maintain
a horse and take their part in war as mounted soldiers. The minimum income of
the third class was two hundred measures, and their name, Teamsters, shows that they were well-to-do peasants who could till
their land with a pair of oxen. The chief magistracies of archon, king, and
polemarch were confined to the first class, but the principle was admitted that
a successful man, although not a Eupatrid, was eligible for the highest offices
if his income amounted to 500 medimni. It was natural
that the rating should be expressed in terms of wealth derived from land; but
it is not a necessary inference that the handicraftsmen were entirely
excluded, or that in order to win political rights they were forced to purchase
estates.
At first this concession of the Eupatrids to their
fellow-citizens did not practically amount to much. Most of the richest men in
the state still belonged to the old clans; but the recognition of wealth as a
political test could not fail to undermine ultimately the privileges of birth.
The organisation of the lower classes into bodies
resembling the Clans of the nobles, and their admission into the Brotherhoods,
have been mentioned. It is probable that the institution of the Thesmothetae also
marks a step in the self-assertion of these classes. The Thesmothetae were a college of six judges, who managed the whole judicial system of Athens.
It was their duty to examine, and call attention to defects in, the laws, and
to keep a record of judicial decisions; and they seem to have taken cognisance of all cases which belonged to the scope of the
Council of Areopagus, except trials for murder. In fact, it looks as if they
were practically a committee of that Council. They were elected annually, and
it has been plausibly supposed that the number of six was determined by the
fact that they originated in a compromise between the orders, three being
Eupatrids, two Georgi, and one a Demiurgos. They were soon associated with the
three chief magistrates, the archon, basileus, and polemarch; and the nine came
to form a sort of college and were called the Nine Archons. Each of the Nine
when he entered on his office took an oath that he would act in accordance with
the laws, and vowed that if he committed any injustice he would dedicate in
gold a man’s statue of life-size. It was a penalty which no archon could have
discharged.
Outside these classes were the smaller peasants who
had land of their own, of which, however, the produce did not amount to two
hundred measures of com or oil, and the humbler handicraftsmen. These were
called Thêtes, the name being
perverted from its proper meaning of “labourers.” The
Thêtes were citizens, but had no political rights. Yet they were beginning to
win a certain public importance. The conditions of a growing maritime trade led
to the development of a navy. As the sea power grew, a new organisation was found necessary, and there can be little doubt that the duty of serving as
marines in the penteconters mainly devolved upon the ThGtes. This gave them a new significance in the state, a
significance which would strengthen their claim to political rights when the
time for pressing that claim should come. We shall hereafter how closely
connected was the democracy of Athens with her sea power; and we can hardly be
wrong in surmising the faint foreshadowings of that connexion at the very beginning of her naval history. Each
of the four tribes was divided, for this purpose, into twelve districts called Naucrariae; each naucraria was probably bound to supply a ship. Thus the
fleet consisted of forty-eight ships. The administration was directed by a body
of naucrari, at the head of which were presidents;
and the organisation might be found convenient for
other than naval purposes. Thus the naucrari formed
an important administrative council.
We see then that, in the middle of the seventh
century, society in Attica is undergoing the change which is transforming the
face of all the progressive parts of Hellas; wealth is competing with descent
as a political test; and the aristocracy of birth seems to be passing into a
timocracy. The power is in the hands of the three chief archons, who always
belong to the class of wealthy nobles, and the Council of Areopagus, which is
certainly composed of Eupatridae. But the classes outside the noble Clans, the
smaller proprietors and the merchants, are beginning to assert themselves and
make their weight felt; possibly the institution of the thesmothetae is due to their pressure. They also obtain admission into the Brotherhoods,
which had been hitherto exclusive. Attic trade is rapidly growing. The
commercial development promotes these democratic tendencies, and has also
entailed the creation of a fleet, which, since the poorest class of citizens
are required to man it, renders that class important and prepares the way for
its political recognition.
As yet, however, the naval establishment of Athens was
but small compared with her neighbours Chalcis and Corinth, or her worship of
daughter cities of Ionia. And Aegina, which had come for a while under the
influence of Argos, outstripped her. It is interesting to find these two
cities, Athens and Aegina, which were in later times to be bitter rivals for
the supremacy in their gulf, in the seventh century taking part in an
association for maintaining the worship of Poseidon in the little island of Calauria, over against Troezen.
Other coast towns of the Saronic and Argolic bays—Epidaurus, Troezen, Hermione, Nauplia, Prasiae—belonged to this sacred union; and the Boeotian
Orchomenus, by virtue of the authority which she still possessed over the
sailors of Anthedon, was also a member. There was no
political significance in the joint Calaurian worship
of these maritime towns; their seamen propitiated Poseidon at Calauria, just as they sacrificed to Panhellenic Zeus on
the far-seen Mountain of Aegina. And they were not grudging votaries. They
built a house for the sea-god in his island; its foundations have been recently
uncovered, and it is one of the earliest stone temples whose ruins have been
found in Greece.
Attica, like the rest of the Greek world, was
disturbed in her economic development by the invention of money. She had
naturally been brought into close commercial relations with her neighbour
Aegina, which at this time began to take a leading part in maritime enterprise.
Accordingly we find Athens adopting the Aeginetan coinage, and using a system
of weights and measures which was almost, if not quite, identical with the
Aeginetan. The introduction of money, which was at first very scarce, and led
to the accumulation of capital in the chests of successful speculators, was
followed by a period of transition between the old system of the direct
exchange of commodities and the new system of a metallic medium; and this
transitional period was trying to all men of small means. But the inevitable
economic crisis did not come at once, though all conditions of social distress
were present, and a conflict between the rich and the poor was drawing steadily
near. An event happened thirty years before the end of the century which shows
that the peasants were still loyal to the existing constitution.
The example of tyranny was infectious, and, as it
flourished at the very door of Athens—in Megara and Corinth,—it was unlikely
that some attempt should not be made at Athens too. A certain Cylon, of noble family, married the daughter of Theagenes,
tyrant ot Megara; and, under Megarian influence and
with Megarian help, he tried to make himself master of the city. Consulting the
Delphic oracle, he was advised to seize the Acropolis on the greatest festival
of Zeus. Cylon, an Olympic victor himself, had no doubt
that the feast of Olympia was meant; but when his plot failed, it was explained
that the oracle referred to the Athenian feast of the Diasia in March, which
was celebrated outside the city. Cylon enlisted in
his enterprise a number of noble youths, and a band of Megarian soldiers were
sent by Theagenes; he had no support among the people. He succeeded in seizing
the Acropolis, but the sight of foreign soldiers effectually quenched any
lurking sympathy that any of the Athenians might have felt for an effort to
overthrow the government The Council of the naucraries summoned the husbandmen from the country, and the summons was readily obeyed. Cylon was blockaded in the citadel, and, after a long
siege, when food and water began to fail, he escaped with his brother from the
fortress. The rest were soon constrained to capitulate. They sought refuge in
the temple of Athena Polias, and left it when the
archons promised to spare their lives. But Megacles, of the Alcmaeonid family,
was archon this year; and of his instigation the pledge was disregarded, and
the conspirators were put to death. Some feud among the clans may have been at
work here. The city was saved from a tyrant, but it had incurred a grave
pollution. Such a violation of a solemn pledge to the suppliants who had
trusted in the protection of the gods was an insult to the gods themselves; and
the city was under a curse till the pollution should be removed. This view was
urged by the secret friends of Cylon and those who
hated the Alcmaeonids. And so it came to pass that while Cylon,
his brother, and their descendants were condemned to disfranchisement and
perpetual banishment, the Alcmaeonids and those who had acted with them were
also tried on the charge of sacrilege and condemned to a perpetual exile, with
confiscation of their property. And the bodies of those of the clan who had
died between the deed of sacrilege and the passing of this sentence were
exhumed and cast beyond the boundary of Attica. The banishment of the
Alcmaeonids had consequences in the distant future, and we shall see how it
comes into the practical politics of Athens two hundred years later. The tale
is also told that the city required a further purification, and that a priest
named Epimenides came from Crete and cleansed it. But
it has been thought doubtful. whether Epimenides is
more than a mythical name like Orpheus, since another story brings him to
Athens again, for similar purposes of atonement, more than a century afterwards
; and then both tales are conciliated by ascribing to the seer a miraculous
sleep of a hundred years.
In the course of the next ten years, the state of the
peasants seems to have changed considerably for the worse. The outbreak of a
war with Megara, in consequence of the plot of Cylon,
aggravated the distress of the rural population; for the Attic coasts suffered
from the depredations of the enemy, and the Megarian market was closed to the
oil-trade. Whether the peasants, who groaned under the existing system, found
leaders and extorted concessions from the government, or whether the ruling
classes themselves saw the danger, and tried to prevent it by a timely
concession, it was at all events decided that a code of law should be drawn up
and written down. Probably men had been clamouring long to obtain this security for life and property; and what the thesmothetae may have already done by recording judicial
decisions in writing was not enough. Dracon was appointed an extraordinary
legislator (Thesmothetes), and empowered to codify
and rectify the existing law. We know only the provisions of that part of his criminal
law which dealt with the shedding of blood; for these provisions were not
altered by subsequent legislation. In later times it was thought that Dracon
revealed to the Athenians how harsh their laws were, and his name became
proverbial for a severe lawgiver. An Athenian orator won credit for his epigram
that Dracon’s laws were written not in ink but in blood. This idea arose from
the fact that certain small offences, such as stealing cabbage, were punished
by death. A broader view, however, of Dracon’s code will modify this view. He
drew careful distinctions between murder and various kinds of accidental or
justifiable manslaughter. In Dracon’s laws we meet a body of fifty-one judges,
called the Ephetae.
They were chosen from the Eupatrids, but it is not clear whether they formed a
part of the Council of the Areopagus or were a wholly distinct body. Those
cases of bloodshed which did not come before the court of the Areopagus were
tried by the Ephetae, in case the shedder of blood
was known. According to the nature of the deed the Ephetae held their court in different places: in the temple of the Delphinian Apollo, in the Palladion at Phaleron,
or at Phreatto, a tongue of land on the Munychian peninsula. This last court was used in the case
of those who were tried for manslaughter committed abroad, and as they might
not set foot on the soil of their country, they had to answer the charge
standing in a boat drawn up near the shore. When the shedder of blood was not
known, the case came before the King in the Prytaneum.
It is unfortunate that we are not informed of Dracon’s
other legislation. We know that the laws relating to debtors were stringent;
the creditor could claim the person of the insolvent debtor. In general, he was
bound to provide for the interests of the rich powerholding class; but it was
at all events an enormous gain for the poor that those interests should be
defined in writing.
Sect.
4. The Legislation of Solon and the Foundation of Democracy
Dracon’s code was something, but it did not touch the
root of the evil. Every year the oppressiveness of the rich few and the
impoverishment of the small farmer were increasing. Without capital, and
obliged to borrow money, the small proprietors mortgaged their lands, which
fell into the hands of capitalists, who lent money at ruinous interest. It must
be remembered that money was still very scarce, and that the peasants had now
to purchase all their needs in coin. Even in Attica the small peasant could not
cope with the larger proprietor. Thus the little farms of Attica were covered
with stones, on which the mortgage bonds were written; the large estates grew
apace; the black earth, as Solon said, was enslaved.
The condition of the free labourers was even more deplorable. The sixth part of the produce, which was their wage,
no longer sufficed, under the new economical conditions, to support life, and
they were forced into borrowing from their masters. The interest was high, the
laws of debt were ruthless, and the person of the borrower was the pledge of
repayment and forfeited to the lender in reduced, to case of inability to pay.
The result was that the class of free labourers was
being gradually transformed into a class of slaves, whom their lords could sell
when they chose.
Thus while the wealthy few were becoming wealthier and
greedier, the small proprietors were becoming landless, and the landless
freemen were becoming slaves. And the evil was aggravated by unjust judgments,
and the perversion of law in favour of the rich and
powerful. The social disease seemed likely to culminate in a political
revolution. The people were bitter against their remorseless oppressors, and
only wanted a leader to rebel. To any student of contemporary politics,
observing the development in other states, a tyranny would have seemed the most
probable solution. A tyranny had already, once at least, and probably more than
once, been averted; and now, as it happened, the masses obtained a mediator,
not a demagogue, a reform, not a revolution. The tyranny, though it was
ultimately to come, was postponed for more than thirty years. The mediator in
the civil strife was Solon, the son of Execestides, a
noble connected with the house of the Medontids. He was a merchant, and
belonged to the wealthiest class in the state. But he was very different from
the Attic Eupatrids, rustic squires, of old fashions and narrow vision. We may
guess that he had not been a home-keeping youth, but had visited the eastern
coasts of the Aegean, whither mercantile concerns might have taken him. At all
events, he had learned much from progressive Ionia. He had imbued himself with
Ionic literature, and had mastered the art of writing verse in the Ionic idiom;
so that he could himself take part in the intellectual movement of the day and
become one of the sages of Greece. He was a poet, not because he was poetically
inspired, like the Parian Archilochus of an earlier, or the Lesbian Sappho of
his own, generation; but because at that time every man of letters was a poet;
there was no prose literature. A hundred years later Solon would have used
prose as the vehicle of his thoughts. His moderate temper made him generally
popular; his knowledge gave him authority; and his countrymen called upon him,
at last, to set their house in order. We are fortunate enough to possess
portions of poems—political pamphlets—which he published for the purpose of
guiding public opinion; and thus we have his view of the situation in his own
words. He did not scruple to speak plainly. The social abuses and the sad state
of the masses were clear to everybody, but Solon saw another side of the
question; and he had no sympathy with the extreme revolutionary agitators who
demanded a redistribution of lands. The more moderate of the nobles seem to
have seen the danger and the urgent need of a new order of things; and thus it
came to pass that Solon was solicited to undertake the work of reform. He
definitely undertook the task and was elected archon, with extraordinary
legislative powers, for the purpose of healing the evils of the state, and
conciliating the classes.
Instead of making the usual declaration of the chief
magistrate, that he would protect the property of all men undiminished, he made
proclamation that all mortgages and debts by which the debtor’s person was
pledged were annulled, and that all those who had become slaves for debt were
free. By this proclamation in that summer, memorable for the rescue of hundreds
of poor wretches into liberty and hope, the Athenians “shook off their
burdens,” and this first act of Solon’s social reform was called the Seisachtheia. The
great deliverance was celebrated by a public feast.
The character of the remedial measures of Solon is
imperfectly known. After the cancelling of old debts he passed a law which
forbade debtors to be enslaved. He fixed a limit for the measure of land which
could be owned by a single person, so as to prevent the growth of dangerously
large estates. And he forbade the exportations of Attic products, except oil.
For it had been found that so much corn was carried to foreign markets, where
the prices were higher, that an insufficient supply remained for the population
of Attica. It is to be observed that at this time the Athenians had not yet
begun to import Pontic corn.
All these measures hit the rich hard, and created
discontent with the reformer; while, on the other hand, he was far from
satisfying the desires and hopes of the masses. He would not confiscate and
redistribute the estates of the wealthy, as many wished. And, though he rescued
the free labourer from bondage, he made no change in
the Sixth-part system, so that the condition of these landless freemen was
improved only in so far as they could not be enslaved, and in so far as the law
limiting exportation affected prices. And Solon was too discreet to attempt to
interfere seriously with the conditions of the money market by artificial
restrictions. He fixed no maximum rate of interest, and his monetary reform
must be kept strictly apart from his social reforms. He replaces the Aeginetan
scale of weights and measures by a scale which was very close to the Euboeic, and he made a corresponding change in the coinage.
The weight of the mina was increased in such a way that 70 of the new drachmae
were equivalent in value to 100 Aeginetan drachmae. This change was brought
into connexion, not with the domestic reform. Nut
with the foreign policy of Athens, to which new propsects were opening. The old coinage attached her to Aegina, with which her relations
were strained, and to her foe Megara the new system seemed to invite her into
the distant fields beyond the sea, where Chalcis and Corinth had led the way in
opening up a new world. For the scale of the Corinthian money was the same as
the Euboeic.
What Solon did to heal the social sores of his country
entitled him to the most fervent gratitude, but it was no more than might have
been done by any able and honest statesman who possessed men’s confidence. His
title to fame as one of the great statesmen of Europe rests upon his reform of
the constitution. He discovered a secret of democracy, and he used his
discovery to build up the constitution on democratic foundations. The Athenian
commonwealth did not actually become a democracy till many years later; but
Solon not only laid the foundations, he shaped the framework. At first sight,
indeed, the state as he reformed it might seem little more than an aristocracy
of wealth—a timocracy—with certain democratic tendencies. He retained the old
graduation of the people in classes according to property. But he added the
Thêtes as a fourth class, and gave it certain political rights. On the three
higher classes devolved the public burdens, and they served as cavalry or as
hoplites. The Thêtes were employed as light-armed troops or as marines. It is
probable that Solon made little or no change in regard to the offices which
were open to each class. Pentacosiomedimni were alone
eligible to the archonship, and for them alone was reserved the financial
office of Treasurer of Athena. Other offices were open to the Hippês and the
Zeugitae, but the distinction in privilege between them is unknown. The Thêtes
were not eligible to any of the offices of state, but they were admitted to
take part in the meetings of the Ecclesia, and this gave them a voice in the
election of the magistrates.
The opening of the Assembly to the lowest class was
indeed an important step in the democratic direction; but it may have been only
the end of a gradual process of widening, which had been going on under the
aristocracy. The radical measure of Solon, which was the very corner-stone of
the Athenian democracy, was his constitution of the courts of justice. He
composed the law-courts out of all the citizens, including the Thêtes; and as
the panels of judges were enrolled by lot, the poorest burgher might have his
turn. Any magistrate on laying down his office could be accused before the
people in these courts; and thus the institution of the popular courts invested
the people with a supreme control over the administration. The people, sitting
in sections as sworn judges, were called the Heliaea—as distinguished from the Ecclesia, in which they gathered
to pass laws or choose magistrates, but were required to take no oath. Having
in its hands both the appointment of the magistrates and the control of their
conduct, the people possessed theoretically the sovereignty of the state; and
the meting out of more privileges to the less wealthy classes could be merely a
matter of time. At first the archons were not deprived of their judicial
powers, and the heliaea acted as a court of appeal; but by degrees the competence of the archons was
reduced to the conduct of the proceedings preliminary to a trial, and the heliaea became both the first and the final court.
The constitution of the judicial courts out of the
whole people was the secret of democracy which Solon discovered. It is his
title to fame in the history of the growth of popular government in Europe.
Without ignoring the tendencies to a democratic development which existed
before him, and without, on the other hand, disguising the privileges which he
reserved to the upper classes, we can hardly hesitate to regard Solon as the
founder of the Athenian democracy. It must indeed be confessed that there is
much in the scope and intention of his constitution which it is difficult to
appreciate, because we know so little of the older constitution which he
reformed. Thus we have no definite record touching the composition of the
Council of the Areopagus, touching its functions as a deliberate body and its
relations to the Assembly, or touching the composition of the Assembly itself.
We can, however, have little doubt that under the older commonwealth the
Council of Elders exerted a preponderant influence over the Assembly, and that
the business submitted to the Assembly, whether by the magistrates or in
whatever way introduced, was previously discussed and settled by the Council.
The founder of popular government could not leave this hinge of the
aristocratic republic as it was. He must either totally change the character of
the Council and transform it into a popular body, or he must deprive it of its
deliberative functions in regard to the Assembly. Solon deprived the Council of
Elders of these deliberative functions, so that it could no longer take any
direct part in administration and legislation. But on the other hand he
assigned to it a new and lofty rôle. He constituted
it the protector of the constitution, and the guardian of the laws, giving it
wide and undefined powers of control over the magistrates, and a censorial
authority over the citizens. Its judicial and religious functions it retained.
In order to bring it into harmony with the rest of his constitution, Solon
seems to have altered the composition of the Council. Henceforward, at least,
the nine archons at the end of their year of office became life-members of the
Council of the Areopagus; and this was the manner in which the Council was
recruited. Thus the Areopagites were virtually appointed by the people in the
Assembly.
Having removed the Council of the Areopagus to this
place of dignity, above and almost outside the constitution, Solon was obliged
to create a new body to prepare the business for the Assembly. Such a body was
indispensable, as the Greeks always recognised; and
it is clear that in its absence enormous powers would have been placed in the
hands of the magistrates, on whom the manipulation of the Assembly would have
entirely devolved. The “probuleutic” Council which
Solon instituted consisted of four hundred members; a hundred being taken from
each of the four tribes, either chosen by the tribe itself or, more probably,
picked by lot. All citizens of the three higher classes were eligible; the
Thêtes alone were excluded. In later days this Council—or rather a new Council
which took its place—gained a large number of important powers, which made it
to all intents an independent body in the state, but at first its functions
seem to have been purely “probuleutic,” and it has
therefore rather the aspect of being merely a part of the organisation of the Assembly. It must always be remembered that it does not represent the
Council of Elders of the Aryan foreworld; it does not
correspond to the Gerusia of Sparta or the Senate of
Rome. But it takes over certain functions which had before formed part of the
duty of the Council of elders; it discusses beforehand the public matters which
are to be submitted to the Assembly.
The use of lot for the purpose of appointing public
officers was a feature of Solon’s reforms. According to men’s ideas in those
days, lot committed the decision to the gods, and was thus a serious method of
procedure—not a sign of political levity, as we should regard it now. But a
device which superstition suggested was approved by the reflexions of philosophical statesmen; and lot was recognised as
a valuable political engine for security against undue influence and for the
protection of minorities. It was doubtless as a security against the undue
influence of clans and parties that Solon used it. He applied it to the
appointment of the chief magistrates themselves. But, religious
though he was, he could not be blind to the danger of taking no human
precautions against the falling of the lot upon an incompetent candidate. He
therefore mixed the two devices of lot and election. Forty candidates were
elected, ten from each tribe, by the voice of their tribesmen; and out of these
the nine archons were picked by lot. It is probable that a similar mixed method
was employed in the choice of the Four Hundred Councillors.
Solon sought to keep the political balance steady by
securing that each of the four tribes should have an equal share in the
government. He could hardly have done otherwise, and yet here we touch on the
weak point in the fabric of his constitution. The gravest danger ahead was in
truth not the strife of poor and rich, of noble lord and man of the people, but
the deep-rooted and bitter jealousies which existed between many of the clans.
While the clan had the tribe behind it and the tribe possessed political
weight, such feuds might at any moment cause a civil war or a revolution. But
it was reserved for a future lawgiver to grapple with this problem. Solon
assuredly saw it, but he had no solution ready to hand; and the evil was
closely connected with another evil, the local parties which divided Attica.
For these dangers Solon offered no remedy, and therefore his work, though
abiding in the highest sense, did not supply a final or even a brief
pacification of the warring elements in the state. He is said to have passed a
law—so clumsy, so difficult to render effective, that it is hard to believe
that such an enactment was ever made—that in the case of a party struggle every
burgher must take a side under pain of losing his civic rights. Solon, if he
was indeed the author of such a measure, sought to avert the possible issues of
political strife by forcing the best citizens to intervene; it was a safeguard,
a clumsy safeguard, against the danger of a tyranny.
It is interesting to observe that in some directions
Solon extended and in others restricted the freedom of the individual. He
restricted it by sumptuary laws and severe penalties for idleness ; he extended
it by an enactment allowing a man who had no heirs of his body to will his
property as he liked, instead of its going to the next of kin. One of Solon’s
first acts was to repeal all the legislation of Dracon, except the laws
relating to manslaughter. His own laws were inscribed on wooden tables set in
revolving frames called axones,
which were numbered, and the laws were quoted by the number of the axon. These
tablets were kept in the Public hall. But copies were made on stone pillars,
called in the old Attic tongue kyrbeis, and kept in the Portico of the King. Every citizen
was required to take an oath that he would obey these laws; and it was ordered
that the laws were to remain in force for a hundred years.
Solon had done his work boldly, but he had done it
constitutionally. He had not made himself a tyrant, as he might easily have
done, and as many expected him to do. On the contrary, one purpose of his
reform was to forestall the necessity, and prevent the possibility, of a
tyranny. He had not even become an aesymnetes—a
legislator (like Pittacus) who for a number of years supersedes the
constitution in order to reform it, and rules for that time with the absolute
power of a tyrant. He had simply held the office of archon, invested, indeed,
with extraordinary powers. To a superficial observer caution seemed the note of
his reforms, and men were surprised, and many disgusted, by his cautiousness.
His caution consisted in reserving the highest offices for men of property,
and. the truth probably is that in his time no others would have been fitted to
perform the duties. But Solon has stated his own principle that the privileges
of each class should be proportional to the public burdens which it can bear.
This was the conservative feature of his legislation; and, seizing on it,
democrats could make out a plausible case for regarding his constitution as
simply a timocracy. When he laid down his office he was assailed by complaints,
and he wrote elegies in which he explains his middle course and professes that
he performed the things which he undertook without favour or fear. “I threw my stout shield,” he says, “over both parties.” He refused
to entertain the idea of any modifications in his measures, and thinking that
the reforms would work better in the absence of the reformer, he left Athens
soon after his archonship and travelled for ten years, partly for mercantile
ends, but perhaps chiefly from curiosity, to see strange places and strange
men.
Though the remnants of his poems are fragmentary,
though the Character recorded events of his life are meagre, and though the
details of his legislation are dimly known and variously interpreted, the
personality of Solon leaves a distinct impression on our minds. We know enough
to see in him an embodiment of the ideal of intellectual and moral excellence
of the early Greeks, and the greatest of their wise men. For him the first of
the virtues was moderation, and his motto was “Avoid excess.” He was in no vulgar
sense a man of the world, for he was many-sided—poet and legislator, traveller and trader, noble and friend of the people. He
had the insight to discern some of the yet undeveloped tendencies of the age,
and could sympathise with other than the
power-holding classes. He had meditated too deeply on the circumstances of
humanity to find power a temptation; he never forgot that he was a traveller between life and death. It was a promising and
characteristic act for a Greek state to commit the task of its reformation to
such a man, and empower him to translate into definite legislative measures the
views which he expressed in his poems.
Solon’s social reforms inaugurated a permanent
improvement. But his political measures, which he intended as a compromise,
displeased many. Party strife broke out again bitterly soon after his
archonship, and only to end, after thirty years, in the tyranny which it had
been his dearest object to prevent. Of this strife we know little. It took the
form of a struggle for the archonship, and two years are noted in which, in
consequence of this struggle, no archons were elected, hence called years of anarchy. Then a certain archon, Damasias, attempted to convert his office into a permanent
tyranny and actually held it for over two years. This attempt frightened the
political parties into making a compromise of some D, sort. Probably it was
agreed that four of the nine archons should be Eupatrids, three Georgi, and two Demiurgi, all of course, possessing the requisite
minimum of wealth. It is unknown whether this arrangement was repeated after
the year of its first trial, but it certainly did not lead to a permanent
reconciliation.
The two great parties were those who were in the main
satisfied with the new constitution of Solon, and those who disliked its
democratic side and desired to return to the aristocratic government which he
had subverted. The latter consisted chiefly of Eupatrids and were known as the
men of the Plain. They were led by Lycurgus, and numbered among them the clan
of the Philaidae—distinguished as the clan of
Hippoclides, the wooer of Agarista, and destined to
become more distinguished still as that of more than one Cimon and Miltiades.
The opposite party of the Coast included not only the population of the coast,
but the bulk of the middle classes, the peasants as well as the Demiurgi, who were bettered by the changes of Solon. They
were led by Megacles, son of Alcmaeon, the same Megacles who married Agarista. For one of Solon’s measures was an act of amnesty
which was couched in such terms that, while it did not benefit the descendants
of Cylon, it permitted the return of the
Alcmaeonidae. Their position severed them from the rest of the Eupatrids and
associated them with the party which represented Solon’s views.
CHAPTER V.
|